Sunday, May 26, 2019
Carr and the Thesis Essay
Edward Carr begins What is History? By saying what he echos history is nonby existence negative. In Carrs words, what history is not, or should not be, is a way of constructing historic accounts that atomic number 18 obsessed with both the items and the documents which are said to contain them. Carr believes that by doing this the profoundly important mold power of the historiographer willing surely be downplayed. Carr goes on to argue in his first chapter- that this downgrading of historiography arose because mainstream historians combined three things first, a simple but very strong boldness that the proper function of the historian was to show the past as it really was blink of an eye, a positivist stress on inductive method, where you first get the points and thus draw conclusions from them and third and this especially in Great Britain a dominant empiricist rationale. Together, these constituted for Carr what still stood for the commonsense view of historyThe empi rical theory of familiarity presupposes a complete separation between subject and object. Facts, like sense-impressions, impinge on the observer from outside and are independent of his consciousness. The process of reception is motionless having received the data, he thus acts on themThis consists of a corpus of ascertained factsFirst get your facts straight, consequently plunge at your peril into the shifting sandpaper of interpretation that is the ultimate wisdom of the empirical, commonsense school of history. 2 Clearly, however, commonsense doesnt work for Mr.Carr.For he sees this as precisely the view one has to reject. unfortunately things begin to get a petty(a) complicated when Carr tries to show the light, since while it seems he has three philosophical ways of leaving about his studies one being epistemic and two ideological his prioritizing of the epistemological over the ideological makes history a science too complex for comprehension to anyone other than hi mself. Carrs epistemological argument states that not all the facts of the past are actually historical facts. Further more, there are vital distinctions to be drawn between the fonts of the past, the facts of the past and the historical facts. That historical facts only become this way is by being branded so by recognized historians. Carr develops this argument as follows What is a historical fact? According to the commonsense view, there are certain basic facts which are the same for all historians and which form, so to speak, the backbone of history the fact, for typesetters case, that the encounter of Hastings was fought in 1066.But this view calls for two observations. In the first place, it is not with facts like these that the historian is primarily concerned. It is no doubt important to know that the great battle was fought in 1066 and not 1065 or 1067The historian must not get these things wrong. But when points of this kind are raised, I am reminded of Housmans remark that true statement is a duty, not a virtue. To praise a historian for his accuracy is like praising an architect for using well-seasoned timber. It is a necessary pin down of his work, but not his essential function.It is precisely for matters of this kind that the historian is entitled to rely on what have been called the auxiliary sciences of history archaeology, epigraphy, numismatics, chronology, and so-forth. 3 Carr thinks that the insertion of such(prenominal) facts into a historical account, and the significance which they will have relative to other selected facts, depends not on any quality intrinsic to the facts in and for themselves, but on the reading of events the historian chooses to give It used to be said that facts speak for themselves. This is, of subscriber line, untrue.The facts speak only when the historian calls on them it is he who decides to which facts to give the floor, and in what pronounce or contextThe only reason why we are interested to know that the battle was fought at Hastings in 1066 is that historians regard it as a major historical event. It is the historian who has decided for his own reasons that Caesars crossing of that petty stream, the Rubicon, is a fact of history, whereas the crossings of the Rubicon by millions of other peopleinterests zero at allThe historian is therefore necessarily selective.The belief in a hard core of historical facts existing objectively and independently of the historian is a preposterous fallacy, but one which it is very hard to eradicate. 4 Following on from this, Carr ends his argument with an illustration of the process by which a slight event from the past is transformed into a historical fact. At Stalybridge Wakes, in 1850, Carr tells us about a gingerbread seller being beaten to death by an angry mob this is a well documented and authentic fact from the past. But for it to become a historical fact, Carr argues that it needed to be slayn up by historians and inserted by them int o their interpretations, thence becoming part of our historical memory. In other words concludes Carr Its status as a historical fact will turn on a question of interpretation. This element of interpretation enters into every fact of history. 5 This is the substance of Carrs first argument and the first site that is easily taken away afterward a quick read his work.Thereby initially surmising that Carr thinks that all history is just interpretation and there are really no such things as facts. This could be an easily mislead conclusion if one ceases to read any further. If the interpretation of Carr stops at this point, then not only are we left with a strong impression that his whole argument about the nature of history, and the status of historical knowledge, is effectively epistemological and skeptical, but we are also not in a good prospect to see why.Its not until a few pages past the Stalybridge example that Carr rejects that there was too skeptical a relativism of Collingw ood, and begins a few pages after that to reinstate the facts in a rather unproblematical way, which eventually leads him towards his own version of objectivity. Carrs other two arguments are therefore crucial to follow, and not because they are explicitly ideological. The first of the two arguments is a perfectly reasonable one, in which Carr is contradictory to the obsession of facts, because of the resulting common sense view of history that turns into an ideological expression of liberalism.Carrs argument runs as follows. The classical, liberal idea of progress was that individuals would, in drill their freedom in ways which took account of the competing claims of others somehow and without too much intervention, move towards a harmony of interests resulting in a greater, freer harmony for all. Carr thinks that this idea was then extended into the argument for a sort of general intellectual laissez-faire, and then more particularly into history.For Carr, the fundamental idea s upporting liberal historiography was that historians, all going about their work in different ways but mindful of the ways of others, would be able to collect the facts and allow the free-play of such facts, thereby securing that they were in harmony with the events of the past which were now truthfully represented. As Carr puts this The nineteenth century was, for the intellectuals of Western Europe, a comfortable period exuding confidence and optimism.The facts were on the whole copacetic and the inclination to ask and answer awkward questions about them correspondingly weakThe liberalview of history had a close affinity with the economic school of thought of laissez-faire also the product of a serene and self-confident outlook on the world. Let everyone get on with his particular job, and the hidden hand would take care of the universal harmony. The facts of history were themselves a demonstration of the supreme fact of a beneficent and apparently infinite progress towards hig her things. 6 Carrs second argument is therefore both straightforward and ideological.His point is that the idea of the freedom of the facts to speak for themselves arose from the happy coincidence that they just happened to speak liberal. But of course Carr did not. Thereby knowing that in the history he wrote the facts had to be made to speak in a way other than liberal (i. e. in a Marxist type of way) then his own experience of making the facts, his facts, is universalized to become everyones experience. Historians, including liberals, have to transform the facts of the past into historical facts by their corrected intervention.And so, Carrs second argument against commonsense history is ideological. For that matter, so is the third. But if the second of Carrs arguments is easy to see, his third and final one is not. This argument needs a little ironing out. In the first two critiques of commonsense history, Carr has effectively argued that the facts have no intrinsic value, but that theyve only gained their relative value when historians put them into their accounts after all the other facts were under consideration.The conclusion Carr drew is that the facts only speak when the historian calls upon them to do so. However, it was part of Carrs position that liberals had not recognized the shaping power of the historian because of the cult of the fact and that, because of the dominance of liberal ideology, their view had become commonsense, not only for themselves, but for practically all historiography. It appeared to Carr that historians seemed to subscribe to the position that they ought to act as the channel through which the facts of the past for their own sake were allowed self-expression.But Carr, not wanting to go the route of his fellow historians, nor wanting to afford to the intellectual complaints about the demise of the experience of originality, says In the following pages I shall try to distance myself from prevailing trends among Western in tellectualsto show how and why I think they have gone astray and to stake out a claim, if not for an optimistic, at any rate for a saner and more balanced outlook on the future. 7 It is therefore this very pointed position which stands behind and gives most, if not all, of the reason for Carrs writing What is History?Carr himself seems to be quite clear that the real demand behind his text was the ideological necessity to re-think and re-articulate the idea of continued historical progress among the conditions and the doubters of his own skeptical days. Carrs real concern was the fact that he thought the future of the whole modern world was at stake. Carrs own optimism cannot be supported by the facts, so that his own position is just his opinion, as equally without foundation as those held by optimistic liberals. Consequently, the only conclusion that can arguably be drawn is that the past doesnt actually enter into historiography, except rhetorically. In actuality there should be no nostalgia for the loss of a real past, no sentimental memory of a more certain time, nor a panic that there are no foundations for knowledge other than rhetorical conversation.
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
No comments:
Post a Comment